Laws of Logic and Reasoning

Plato’s Laws
Plato’s laws can be expressed as follows; 1. Nothing can become greater or less, either in number or magnitude, while remaining equal to itself. 2. It is impossible to have an increase or decrease of anything without addition or subtraction. 3. Nothing of a physical nature can exist without becoming and having become. In other words, physical existence necessitates a caused beginning. This law is sometimes refered to The Law of sufficient Reason.
On the surface, these statements seems ridiculously simple. However, the implications are far-reaching. Taken as a whole, these laws express that physical existence cannot cause itself. They also allude to any change in a physical object must be the result of forces outside of that object.

Aristotle’s Laws
- The Law of Identity. This law states that everything is identical to itself. Symbolically, if A represents a true statement then “A = A”. In other words, if statement A is a truth statement then it is always true when presented in its original context. This also holds for a false statement. If statement A is false then it is always false when presented in its original context. An example would be to say “George Washington was the first President of the United States under the Constitution” is a true statement. It is equal to “The first President of the United States under the Constitution was George Washington”. The second statement is true because it is equal to the first which is true. Caution must be given to make sure which “George Washington” is being referred to. If the first statement is true, the second might be false if the person intended is a different “George Washington”. In this case, even though the wording is the same, the statements are not equal because they do not pertain to the same context.
- The Law of Non-Contridiction. This law asserts that a proposition (or statement) and its negation cannot both be true at the same time and in the same sense or location. For example, “I have only one cat and its name is Morris” and “I have only one cat and its name is not Morris” cannot both be true simultaneously in the same location. Symbolically, a negation is represented by ~. So A and ~A cannot be both true at the same time or location. Again, the importance of sense, time, and location cannot be over emphasized. “I have only one cat and its name is Morris” and “I have only one cat and its name is not Morris” can certainly both be true if the propositions are made at different times.
- The Law of the Excluded Middle. Perhaps the most referenced of Aristotle’s laws, the Law of the Excluded Middle, states that for any proposition, either the proposition or its negation must be true; there is no third option. The law gets its name from the fact there is no “middle ground” between true and false. For example, “Today is Wednesday” or “Today is not Wednesday” must be true; there are no other possibilities. Symbolically we could write A≠~A. The Law of the Excluded Middle does not apply to A and ~B, A and ~C and so on.
In order to fully apply Aristotle’s Laws, there must be a way to compare one proposition, or statement, to another. It seems unlikely that Aristotle did not understand this so it may be that he simply took comparisions for granted. However, all studies of logic start off with the following:
property P, then either A has more of property P than B, or A has less of property P than B or A and B are indifferent to
each other. It is important to note here that comparisons are based on observations or assumed values. This also
introduces the very real possibility of bias when deciding on values and outcomes. It also demands a consistent way
of determing value. Let’s say that A is a coffee cup in my house and B is an antique clock. Both have value (which
would be property P). But how do you determine value? Is it the resale amount in dollars, sentimental value, usage
value? Either A or B could be of more value depending on the determining factor(s).
Types of Reasoning
A→B (1st or Major Premise)
C→A (2nd or Minor Premise)
C→B (Conclusion)
All men are mortal.
Socrates is a man.
Socrates is mortal.
It is very important to distinguish between validity and truth. A conclusion may be valid (meaning that the conclusion has been constructed correctly) but still be false if one or both premises are false.
Socrates is a man. (true Minor Premise)
Socrates is a fish. (valid but false Conclusion)
All men are mortal. (true Major Premise)
My dog Riley is not a man. (true Minor Premise)
My dog Riley is mortal (invalid but true Conclusion)